03.06.2013 Views

Do Scientific Objects Have a History? - Bruno Latour

Do Scientific Objects Have a History? - Bruno Latour

Do Scientific Objects Have a History? - Bruno Latour

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Spring 1996 V) Nl<br />

COAAfNON KNOWLEDGE<br />

Cor-uuNs<br />

Prague Spring, Much Later<br />

: . , , -..<br />

nrpaa uqncz<br />

I<br />

Die Marken besagen alles!<br />

Colin Richmond<br />

3<br />

ARrrcres<br />

The Abuses of Memory<br />

Tzaetan Todorop<br />

Translated by Mei Lin Chang<br />

6<br />

On Memory and Horror<br />

A Response to Tzvetan Todorov<br />

G. M. Tamâs<br />

27<br />

Heroes and Guinea Pigs<br />

Daniel S. Milo<br />

Translated by Stephen E. Lewis<br />

33<br />

The Death Drive <strong>Do</strong>es Not Think<br />

Robat Snith<br />

,9<br />

<strong>Do</strong> Scientifrc <strong>Objects</strong> <strong>Have</strong> a <strong>History</strong>?<br />

Pasteur and \Thitehead in a Bath of<br />

Lactic Acid<br />

<strong>Bruno</strong> Lataar<br />

Translated by Lydia Davis<br />

-/<br />

/o<br />

Rousseau in the Restaurant<br />

Rebecca L. Spang<br />

9)<br />

Oakeshott, Berlin, and Enlightenment<br />

John Gral<br />

109<br />

SrRrarrv Sylrposruu<br />

Countertransference and<br />

the Humanities<br />

Countertransference and Artistic<br />

Appreciation<br />

Joseph Sandler<br />

r34<br />

Porrny/FrcrroN<br />

from Bad <strong>History</strong><br />

Banett lilatten<br />

r46<br />

The Long View<br />

Cbarles O. Hartman<br />

r49<br />

In Loveland<br />

Gilbert Sonentino<br />

119<br />

Revlrws<br />

The Kariakin Phenomenon<br />

Caryl Emerson<br />

t6r<br />

Little Reviews<br />

Rath Morse<br />

Daaid Bromwich<br />

Colin Richnond<br />

Anne Higonnet<br />

Robert C. Euans<br />

AndrEu Delbanco<br />

Howard Hampton<br />

Jobn Bayley<br />

Larissa Taylor<br />

Susan Reynolds<br />

Jake Milgran tYien<br />

AnnJessie Van Sant


<strong>Do</strong> ScrnNTrFrc Oslncrs Havn a Hrsronv?<br />

PASTEUR AND \qHITEHEAD IN A BATH OF<br />

LÂCTIC ACID<br />

<strong>Bruno</strong> Lafour<br />

Translated by Lydia Davis<br />

But in the rcal world it is more important that a propotition be interesting than it be true.<br />

The importance ol truth is, that it adds t0 interest.<br />

It must be remembered that tbe phrase actual world is /ike yesterday and totnorrma, in tbat it<br />

alters its neaning according t0 standpzint.<br />

-Alfred N. Whitehead, Prccess and Reality<br />

f n ^ ....n, issue o[ Comnon Knowledge,'I followed in some detail the progressive<br />

I<br />

I transformation of a tiny piece of Amazonian forest into scienti6c knowledge. To<br />

do so, I multiplied mediations, replacing the huge vertical gap between words and<br />

world with a horizontal set oftiny translations from one representational medium to<br />

anorher. In that article, the main activity was from the human side, from the scientists<br />

and their instruments, from maps and diagrams and collections. No matrer how many<br />

intermediary steps I unfolded, those steps were still portrayed by me as a way to gain<br />

access to the forest "out there." More exactly, even though the forest "out there" was<br />

reformatted in my paper as a thing circulating "inside" the network of science, this<br />

circulating thing could not be imagined otherwise rhan passiue. The Boa Vista forest,<br />

in itself, was doing nothing.<br />

It is this passivity that I want to try to overcome in this essay. At the risk of taxing<br />

the patience of the readers of Common Knowledge, I will consider another piece of hard<br />

science-borrowed this time, in honor of the cenrenary of his death, from the story of<br />

Pasteur and the history of fermentation. \What has made so many modern philosophers<br />

and theorists shun realism is rhe impoverished role assigned by realist philosophers to<br />

objects ofscientifrc discovery which apparently had no other function, no other onto-<br />

logical life, than to wait silently in the dark before shutting the mouths of the human<br />

agents discussing them. This silent and silencing function was what irritated, and<br />

'"The 'Pédolil' of Boa Vista: A Photo-Philosophical Montage," Common Knruhdge 4 (SPring 1995):<br />

144-t1 / .


DO SCIENTIFIC OBJECTS HAVE A HISTORYI 71<br />

with good reason, those who could not believe in unmediated access to rruth. In rheir<br />

eyes, science is interesting not because it offers unmediated access ro tl-re world, but<br />

rather another form of mediation, of transcendence, of truth warmly clothed.<br />

The question I wanc to ask is whether it is possible to develop a sort o[realism rhat<br />

would offer the agents of the world a more inceresting role than that of passive objecr.<br />

Strangely, not many philosophers are interested in this metaphysical quesrion. No<br />

matter whether they worship or hate science, most rhinkers take for granted that scien-<br />

tilic objects, accessible or not, behave as realisrs believe them to [shavs-1h21 i5, In a<br />

passive and indifferent manner, wholly impervious to human history. The only alrerna-<br />

tives that most philosophers can imagine are animism and arnthropomorphism, horrors<br />

to which they always prefer the canonical version of objects seen sub specie scientiae.<br />

A. N. Whitehead is one of the interestingl exceptions, and it is his "historical realism,"<br />

though largely out of fashion, that I want to use as my guide or goad for this explora-<br />

cion. But since I am only half a philosopher, I need an empirical site in order not ro<br />

lose myself in questions that quickly become too deep for me: my project, then, will<br />

be to imagine how \Whitehead would have accounred for Pasteur's understanding o[<br />

the discovery of lactic-acid fermentation in 1858.<br />

Sollr REcpNT CoNTRovERsTES rN ScTENCE Sruorrs<br />

The sintple nltilil 0f an endaring sultstance sastaining persistent qtalities. either essen-<br />

tia/ly or accidenta/ly, expresses a asefa/ abstract for many pn'poses af /{e. Bnt ubetteuer<br />

u,e try t0 urc it at a fundamental statentent af tl.te nature of things, it prorcs itself mistaken.<br />

It arose fron a nistake and has nn,er sucreeded in any af its applications.2<br />

This critique of substantialism. so important for Whitehead, could be shared by nu-<br />

merous historians and sociologists of science, but ior very different reasons. In an ac-<br />

count ofa discovery, one should nat, ^ccording to students ofscience, refer ro a sub-<br />

stance external to the human work involved in order to explain its genesis.r Of course,<br />

like Kant, most contemporary historians, in order to avoid the extremes of idealism,<br />

do not deny the existence ofsuch a subsrance, but rhey wish to emphasize the concrete<br />

attributes only of the mind that knows or, in more recent hisroriography, only o[ che<br />

practice of the scientific group rhat man.iiulares and demonsrraces che subscance<br />

within the closed and local precinct ol the laboratory.l According; ro them, in order to<br />

fo<br />

'Alfred N. Whitehead, Procer anl Rea/it1:.\u Essal tnCosrtulogl lNew York: Free Press, lIc)29) l9l8),<br />

rThe canonical description of this principle qan be t-ound in Harry M. Collins.ChangingOrdu: Repl)catiat<br />

and Induction in Scientif;c Practice (London: Sage, l!85).<br />

'The<br />

most developed examples can be firund in Steven Shapin and Simon Schaffer, LtLiatban and the Air,<br />

PmQ: Hobbes, Bayte and tbe Experinental Ly'i (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1985), and, more re-<br />

cenrly, Christian Licoppe, Zz Forrtttnn J, /,t ptttiqrc rLrtrrQqre (Paris: La Découverre, 1 996).


18 COMMON KNO\flLEDGE<br />

criticise substantialism, one must quite simply abstain from giaing a role to nonhamans in<br />

the story ofa discovery and instead consrrucr the account exclusively with reference to<br />

rhe praccices, the places, rhe insrrumenrs, rhe auchorities, rhe insr.irurions, and rhe<br />

historical events furnished by the conrext. Such historians hope that a multitude of<br />

small determinations when added to one anorher will count for as much as rhe always-<br />

already-there substance of the old-fashioned accounts o[ discoveries. However, as Isa-<br />

belle Stengers has clearly shown in a recenr book,5 there is something unlikely for rhe<br />

practicing scientist in this approach, something unrealistic, nor only in the philosophi-<br />

cal sense of the word but also in the common meaning of improbable. Someching<br />

essential seems missing from the account. Is it precisely essence that is lacking? No,<br />

and it is $/hitehead's interest to imagine a realism without substance, a raàical hisrori-<br />

cai realism ("The Castle Rock of Edinburgh exists from momenr co momenc, and from<br />

century to century, by reason ofthe decision effected by its own historic route ofante-<br />

cedent occasions.")6<br />

It has seemed necessary to some of us to devise what we call in our jargon "prin-<br />

ciples of symmetry" in order to do justice-without falling back on essenrialism-ro<br />

the feeling scientists and common sense share that somerhing is missing from accounrs<br />

of science that consider only the human side. The first principie of symmetry de-<br />

manded that historians judge accounrs of discovery fairly by rrearing on terms of<br />

equality scientists who have been wrong and those who have been right.' This prin-<br />

ciple, which is opposed ro rhe French episremological tradition rhat demands one dis-<br />

tinguish "out-of date science" from "sanctioned science,"8 permitred nice effects of<br />

historical drama. The victories of Boyle over Hobbes, of Newton over Descarres, or of<br />

Pasteur over Pouchet, no longer differed from rhe provisional victories of Napoleon<br />

over Tsar Alexander, or ofClinton over Bush. The history ofscience ceased to be distin-<br />

guished from history plain and simple.<br />

The price paid for this reuni6cation was very high. The principle of iimired symme-<br />

try does not equalize the possibilities of the victors (rationaliry) and the vanquished<br />

(irrationality) except in that the principle forbids borh protagonists access ro rhe very<br />

phenomena that they both consider their only reason for being. There is something<br />

heroic in this: nature, the symmetrical historians all say with a yogi's ascericism, does<br />

noc intervene in the interpreracions we make with respect to it.<br />

tlsabelle<br />

Stengers, L'lu'ention dzs scieues modunes (Paris: La Découverte, 1993).<br />

6\Thitehead. 41.<br />

'See<br />

David Bloor, Krcu'ledge and Soiial lnagery lChicago: Universiry ofChicago Press, [1976] l99l). For<br />

a more recent justi6cation, see rhe preface to rhe second edition<br />

sSee<br />

Georges Can guilhem,ldeolag'and Rationalitl, in tbe <strong>History</strong> of tbe Life Sciene:, trans. Arthur Goldhammer<br />

(Cambridge: MIT Press, I19681 1988), tbr an exrreme example. See also, more recenrly, G. Canghuilhem,<br />

A Vital Rationalist: Selected Vrittngs. rraos. A. Goldhammer, ed. François Delaporre (New York: Zone<br />

Books,1994).


DO SCIENTIFIC OBJECTS HAVE A HISTORY? 19<br />

one can understand the motives of historians who are pâfrisans of symmetry-they<br />

are reacting againsr the abuses ofsubstantialists who are content to exPlain that vlctors<br />

in the history of science won because they were more rational or had better access to<br />

rhe nature of things. By insisting, for the first time, on the difficulties of the experi-<br />

menr, on the uncerrainties of the instruments, on the irremediable localization of the<br />

merhods, on rhe ambiguity of interpretations, on the importance of a community of<br />

more or less credible colleagues, the constructivist historians find it easy to ridicule<br />

those who believe they benefit from immediate access to the real and who take social<br />

of cognitive habits that date only from yesterday to be the permanent essence ofthings.<br />

It is imporrant, however, to avoid pressing ascericism ro rhe poinr ofanorexia, and<br />

this is where another, more general, principle of symmetry becomes necessary.e No<br />

longer is it a matter of equalizing the possibilities for success of the victors and the<br />

vanquished by evenhandedly forbidding both groups access to the real but rather of<br />

equalizing by allowing all groups to construct simultaneously and symmetrically both<br />

their natural reality and their social reality. Like yogis who have been without food too<br />

long and forced to sleep too many nights on beds of nails, one Ênally allows victors<br />

and vanquished alike to gorge themselves on reality and sleeP in featherbeds. This<br />

shift enables recovery from Kantianism since one no longer has to choose, in order to<br />

explain a discovery, between privileged access to the real and determination through<br />

thousands ofsmall social or practical causes. One sees in effect that the real as a reserve<br />

or anchor against idealism had meaning only by contrast with the knowing mind (or<br />

the laboratory, or the paradigm). For every Copernican revolution, there is a countef-<br />

revolution and a half. Discoverers establish at once what they afe, the world in which<br />

rhey are situated, and the numerous social, practical, and historical causaiities comPat-<br />

ible with rhe type of phenomena with which they are populating the collective. The<br />

differences among ontological, epistemological, and sociologicai questions become in-<br />

distinct. The question becomes: In which socionatural world do we agfee to live? The<br />

principle of generalized symmerfy does not abolish the principle of limited symmerfy,<br />

bur extends it to questions about nature and about society, and thus allows a new<br />

object to appear-the co/lectiae of humans and nonhumans.r0<br />

This solution, however, does not have the meraphysics of its ambirions. while no<br />

longer anthropomorphic, it remains as fragile as the meaning given to the wotd collec-<br />

tiae. If one means by that word the demiurgic activity of researchers in engendering<br />

not only nacure but also society and the history in which they are situated, one comes<br />

dangerously close to the tales of the absolute idealists that believed they couid go<br />

,,beyond Kanr." \Thereas if ir is semioric proliferation thar endows humans, nonhu-<br />

eSee <strong>Bruno</strong> <strong>Latour</strong>.rYe Hat,e Neter Beer Ilodern, trans. Catherine Porter (Cambridge: Harvard University<br />

Press, 1991), for a presentation of this principlc and its consequences for anthropology.<br />

'oSee B. Larour. "On Technical N{ediation,' Courron Knouledge 1 $aII 1994):29-61.


80 COMMON KNOITLEDGE<br />

mans (i.e., objects in circulation), enunciative positions, and the contexts inscribed in<br />

texts with certain properties, then we are awash in discourse, in a sea of positions<br />

without subjects, and we drift farther from the realism that we were aiming for. The<br />

"superman" of the 6rst (the demiurgic) account is abruptly followed by the "death of<br />

man" in the second. In a third account the activity of researchers is a matter of allowing<br />

nonhumans to proliferate in society as subjects, in which case we run the risk o[ natu-<br />

raliztng the whole of history without any longer being able to endow obiects with<br />

their uncertainty, their transcendence, their "tremolo." This third account relies on a<br />

will to power to anchor discourse and action in biology or in physics.<br />

In order to be sure of escaping these three perils-being trapped in society. in<br />

language, 61 In n4gu1g-we must leave behind for a momenc the ambiguity of the<br />

word co//ectitte and abandon the notions of actors, actions, subjects, objects, humans,<br />

and nonhumans that have provisionally served to enabie our escape from Kantianism.<br />

Thus we must dare, Iike rùThitehead,<br />

to have commerce with metaphysics despite the<br />

embargo declared against it by analytic philosophy as well as by constructivism.<br />

How PasrruR STAGES HIS o\rN DtscoveRv or<br />

THE LACTIC ACTO FENUEN-r<br />

In 18)8, sometime after having discovered the fermentation of brewer's yeast, Pasceur<br />

relates, in a celebrated report to the Académie des sciences, the discovery of a yeast<br />

peculiar to lactic acid.lt Today, Iactic fermentation is no longer an obiect ofdiscussion,<br />

and one can order by mail any quantities of yeast for dairies, creameries, and cheese<br />

manufacturers the world over. But one has only to "place oneself in the conditions of<br />

the period" to measure the originality of Pasteur's report, and chus the reward he can<br />

claim for his pains. In the middle ofthe nineteenth century, in scientiÊc circles influ-<br />

enced by Liebig's chemistry, the claim that a speciÊc microorganism could explain<br />

fermentation amounted ro a srep backward, since it was through ridding itself of ob-<br />

scure vitalist explanations that chemistry had only just won its laurels.r2 Fermentatton<br />

could and had been explained, without the intervention of any living thing what-<br />

soever, in a purely chemical way by the degradation of inert substances. In any case,<br />

specialists in lactic fermentation had never seen microorganisms inseparably associated<br />

with the rransformation of susar:<br />

ttThe English rext is "Pasteur's Study of Fermenrarion" in HaruatdCaseHistuies it Exprimental Science.<br />

vol. 2, ed. James B. Conant (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1957), 453-60. A fuller semiotic analysis<br />

of Pæteur's repon can be found in my "Pasteur on Lactic Acid Yeast: A Partial Semiotic Analysis,"<br />

Confgurations 1 (January 199)): \27-42. For a general presentation ofPasteur's career, the besr source rs<br />

now Gerald Geison,Tbe Priuate Science of Louis Pasteur (Prrnceron: Princeton University Press, 1991). In this<br />

article, I am concentrating on the text in order to extract from it its various ontologies, and not concerning<br />

myself with other material (æ I did fbr the Boa Vista tbrest; Conman Knou'ledge 4:1,1{4-87) that would<br />

connect me more securely to Pasreur's Iaboratory and method.<br />

"For a descriprion of the chemists and their professional ideologies at the time, see Bernadette<br />

Bensaude-Vincent and L Stengers, Hi:toire de la chiilie (Paris: La Découverte, 1 991).


DO SCIENTIFIC OBJECTS HAVE A HISTORY2 81<br />

lJntil nou minate ruearcbes baue beenunable to discover the dnelopment of organized<br />

life. Obsen,ers u,ho hate idcntifud some organisms haue at tbe sane time fotmd that rhry<br />

u,ere acciàental and detrimental to ilse process.<br />

Tbe faas Tl:en seem very favorable to the ideas of Liebig or to tbote of Berzelias. In the<br />

eya of the former d ferment is an anstable substance that decomposes and therebl excites<br />

fennentation in consequence of its a/teration u'bich commmicdrer d disinte&rating distar-<br />

l)ance t0 the nolecular grotp of the fernentable matter According to Liebig, silch is the<br />

primary cause of all fernentations and the origin of nost contagious diseases. Bazelias<br />

be/ia,es that the cbenical act offermentation is to be referted to the action ofcontact. These<br />

lpinilns gain more credit daily. . . . These worhs all agree in rejecting the idea of<br />

some sorr of influence frcm organization and life as a caase 0f the phenlnena that<br />

ue are considerizg. (Emphasis added.)<br />

And Pasteur quietly adds: "I have been led to an enrirely different point ofview"!1r<br />

The discoverer will appear all the more involved in the process because he will have<br />

everyone againsr him, the unanimous opinion of the chemists as well as rhe scrupulous<br />

research ofthe specialists. The discoverer does not lift rhe veil behind which the yeast<br />

in lacric fermenration has always been hiding. Like the srory of General de Gaulle<br />

rising from obscurity to triumph, the discoverer's srory can be rold as a tale of victory.<br />

But Pasteur's acr was not rhe imposition o[a framework or vision on powerless mat-<br />

ter-though he later posed the problem to himself in these terms (as we shall see). He<br />

states, in fact, rhat he has been led to a poinr of view. His activity consists in allowing<br />

himself to be carried along by the "propensity of things," to adopr François Jullien's<br />

beautiful expression.Ia Even when Pasteur acts to cause the yeast to emerge, in opposi-<br />

tion to the convictions of the rest of the world, he srill allows himself to be led by<br />

things-thus mingling once again the fate of a subject and an object.<br />

For politicai and military history resources exist that allow one to weigh the respec-<br />

tive roles of longae durée, opportrtnrry, circumstances, chance, individual genius, and<br />

Ênally the arrribution of responsibility to a few individual geniuses. However, when it<br />

is a matter ofaccounting for beings who have been invented or discovered, the histo-<br />

rian of science becomes more rimid, more hesiranr than his colleagues. The hisrorian<br />

of science accosrs one monscer more than che hiscorian plain and simple: however greac<br />

may be the heterogony of factors that history summons, it is never as grear as in the<br />

history ofscience, where one must inregrare rhe short life ofPasreur, the longer span<br />

of the Second Empire or of chem.istry, the even longer existence of alcoholic or lactic<br />

fermentations (which go back ro Neolithic times), and rhe existence, infrnitely longer,<br />

'J. B. Conant, 455.<br />

'aSurprising resonances exist between \Thitehead, op. cit., and. this admirable book on Chinese philoso-<br />

phy: François Jullien, Tbe Propensity oJ'Tbings: Tou'ard a H istory of Effvary in China (New York: Zone Books,<br />

r99t).


82 COMMON KNO'i/LEDGE<br />

absolutely longer, of lactic acid yeast, always already presenr. Once discnered by Pasteur<br />

in 1857,lactic acid yeast has always already been there, from Neolirhic times in the<br />

gourds of homo sapiens to the presenr in che whey rhat is souring in all rhe dairies on<br />

earth. How should one go about historicizing the creation of a being that seems to<br />

overflow its historical framework immediately, to go back through rhe whole of time<br />

and spread through the whole of spaceT Historians are used to dealing wichche /angae<br />

durée, l:ut how to deal with timelessness?<br />

The only solution consists in bestowing historicity on all elements that enrer inro<br />

an account. Young Louis Pasteur of Lille counrs as an episode in the destiny, in the<br />

essence, in the trajectory of lactic yeast: The absurdity ofa premise like this, the scan-<br />

dal it may provoke, is broughr home if, instead of to yeast, srill close to rhe agirated<br />

history of living things, rhe premise is applied co gravitation or cosmoiogy. Newton<br />

happened ro universal gravitarion? The European Cenrer for Nuclear Research hap-<br />

pened to the Big Bang?<br />

If, once again seeking refuge in rhe cozy Kantian framework, one were to speak<br />

only of represewarion, there would be no difficulry here. Pasteur would be said to trans-<br />

form the ideas that chemists and dairymen have formed "about" lactic fermenrarion,<br />

much as Newton modified our ideas about the action of disrant celestial bodies. One<br />

would return more easily ro history if one remained exclusively among humans wirh<br />

their representations, their visions ofthe world, their more or less passionate interests.<br />

The history ofscience, social or intellectual, could be deployed, like most ofanthropoi-<br />

ogy, with a boldness all the greater because it would be limited ro representarrons<br />

alone, leaving the phenomena rhemselves out of reach. But, given generalized symme-<br />

try we want to reach rhe phenomena, ro emerge from the childhood home of ideaiism<br />

and rediscover, with realism, the risks of ontology wirhout losing the uncertainties of<br />

history or the localizarion of methods.tt \7e musr rherefore explore this path, however<br />

bizarre it may appear, and speak of Pasreur as an euent that occars to lactic acid.<br />

Snvrnal ONror-ocrss \?rrH VaRtngLr Gsol{stRrrs<br />

What seemed absurd in a metaphysics of essence and attributes can become child's<br />

play for "an ontology of evenrs and relacions."t6 In \Whitehead's vocabulary, Pasteur's<br />

laboratory appears to us an occasion offered to trdjectlries ofentities that inberit preceàing<br />

"S7hat is involved, in fàct, is atrributing to rhe following passage in Kuhn an ontology, where, in his<br />

understanding o[ it, it hæ a psychosocial meaning: "[T]hough rhe world does not change with a change of<br />

paradigm," he writes, "tbe scientist aftmtard umhs in a diffrent uorld, Nevertheless, I am convinced that we<br />

must Iearn to make sense of statements that at least resemble these. \ùfhat occurs during a scientifrc revolution<br />

is not fully reducible to a reinrerpretation of individual and srable dara." Thomas S. Kuhn, Tbe Strrctare<br />

ofScient$cRaolations(Chiczgo: UniversityofChicagoPress, t1962]1970),121.<br />

L6I am borrowing these terms from the excellent article byJohn B. Cobb, "Alfred North !7hitehead,"<br />

in Famdtrs of Con$ructiue Plrtîtzdern Philuopby, ed. David Ray Grif6n (Albany: State University of New York<br />

Press,1993).


DO SCIENTIFIC OBJECTS HAVE Â HISTORY2 83<br />

circumstances by deciding to persevere in a new w^y of being. Certain entiries will<br />

travel through the laboratory as stabilized practices. This is the case oflactic acid itself:<br />

LacticacidwasdiscoueredbyScbeelein 1780 insotredu,bey. Hriprocedure forremouing<br />

it from the u'bey is still today tbe best one can follou.<br />

In a footnote, Pasteur adds:<br />

First he reduced the whey to an eigbth of its uolume by euaporation. He frkered it and<br />

sarurared it uith line t0 precipirare tbe phoQhate of line. The liqaid was then filtered<br />

and àiluted u,ith three times its weight of uater; into tbit be potred oxalic acid drop by<br />

drop to precipitare all the lime. He evaporated the Iiquid to the consistency ofhoney. . . .<br />

(Emphasis added.)<br />

Even here, the acid is not presented as a substance durable in time and defined by<br />

its attributes but rather by a collection ofverbs referring to laboratory gestures. Acid<br />

is ultimately aprocedure, a recipe, and is coextensive with a course of acrion. The fact<br />

that the list of operations is long hardly matters, since each of rhem is parr of rhe<br />

routine of a well-equipped chemistry laboratory. The interlocking of che subprograms<br />

does not make the essence fragile because skillful chemists have no trouble understand-<br />

ing the gestures for frltering, evaporating, precipitating, and because they take their<br />

arrangement as monoiithrc.<br />

The same is not crue for the yeast thar the entire scientific communiry found so<br />

dubious in 1817:<br />

If one examines carefully an ordinary lactic fumentation, there are cases wltere one can<br />

Ênd on top of the dcposit of the cbalk and nitrogenoas nataial spo:s 0f d gray substance<br />

uhich sometines form a layer on the sarface of the deposit. At othu tines, this sabttance is<br />

fomd<br />

adhering t0 the t/p\er sides of the uesre/, uhere it has been canied fu effewescence.<br />

Undu the microscope, wben one is notforeuarned, it is hardly possible to distinguish it<br />

from casein, disaggregated ghten, etc,; in sltort, nothing indicates tbat it is d sepa.rdte<br />

material or that it originated during thefumentation, lts apparent weight aluays rentains<br />

very little dr clmpared to that of the nitrogenoas nnterial originally necessary for the<br />

carrying out of the pracess. F inally, very often it r so mixed witb tbe mass of cdrein and<br />

chalhtbattbaewou/dbenorearznt0suspect itsexiitence. ltisnnerthelessthissubstance<br />

that plays the principal role. (Emphasis added.)<br />

The very existence ofthe yeast is in question, as rhar oflactic acid is not. There are<br />

no routinized gestures that would allow one to assure the regular presence of yeast.<br />

The entity is defrned only by a "degree zero" ofexistence, appearing as "spots o( a gray<br />

substance which sometimes form a layer on the surface of the deposit." One could<br />

scarcely exist less! The contrast appears all the stronger in the act of defiance with<br />

which the quotation above concludes. In opposition to Liebig and Berzelius, as we<br />

have seen, Pasteur was "led to an entirely different point of view." This thought process


84 COMMON KNOVLEDGE<br />

depends on a conversion by which a creature of whom one does not have "reason to<br />

suspect its existence" "nevertheless<br />

plays the principal role"!<br />

In order to follow how the yeast-criticized by everyone, invisible, a poor spot at<br />

the bottom of a glass vessel-will soon become the "only thing responsible" for lactic<br />

fermentation, the expressions "subject" and "object" must become, as one may imag-<br />

ine, of litcle use. Pasteur plays his large part in this affair, as do the yeast, Liebig, and<br />

the dairymen. \7e do not observe a man endowed with faculties discovering a creature<br />

defined by attributes. \7e see a body with multiple and partial members seeking to<br />

bring about in its laboratory, through a series oftrials, a regular succession ofactions:<br />

I am going to shou, f.rst of all, hc,u, to isalate it and prepare it in a pare state.<br />

I extract the solable part fron breu'er\ yeast, bl trea.ting the yeast for some time wirb<br />

fifteen to tu)entJ timer its weight 0f uater at the temperatare of boiling uater. The /iquid,<br />

a clmplex szlution of albuminous and mineral material. is carefully filtered. Altout ffty<br />

to one handred granx ofsugar are then dissolaed in each liter, some chalk is added, and a<br />

trace of the gray materia/ I haue just mentilned extracted frlm a good, ordinary lactic<br />

fermentation ri sprinkled in; then one raises the temperatare to 30 or 35 degræs Centi-<br />

grade. It is also good to introduce a carrent of carbonic acid )n order to expel the air<br />

fron the flask, which is Jitted u,ith a bent exit tube immersed ander u,ater. On the aery next<br />

day a liaely and regularfermentatizn is manifest. (Emphasis added.)<br />

In the laboratory, the body ofPasteur, careful and skilled, serves as the occasion, the<br />

circumstance, the concrescence of the enduring establishment of lactic fermentatron.<br />

Through gestures (filtering, dissolving, adding), ingredients (brewer's yeast, solution,<br />

chalk), hxtures (faucets, receptacles, ovens, tubes), instruments for measuring (ther-<br />

mometers, scales, thermostars), and little tricks of the profession, fermentation be-<br />

comes visible and stable. At this stage of variation, the essenc€ of fermentation rs coex-<br />

tensive with the deployment of practical and locai circumstances.<br />

Granting historicity to the yeast, in this instance, goes much further than a simple<br />

return to the contingencies of the period in question. It is no longer a matter simply<br />

of going back to Pasteur, trembling in his laborarory with fear that he might lose his<br />

fermentation and that his yeast might not be a "correlative to life." The lactic fermenta-<br />

tion is also trembling. This controlled manifestation, "lively and regular," has never<br />

happened before, since the world began, to yeast, anywhere. The small iaboratory of<br />

the dean of the faculty of science at Lilie also constitutes a decisive juncture in the<br />

trajectory of this fermentation since here it becomes visible and pure. It is no longer<br />

only Pasteur who alters his "representation" of the fermentation, but the fermenrarion<br />

itself(in its being, in its history, in its ascents and descents) that modifies irs manifesta-<br />

tions.<br />

If Pasteur hesitates, the fermencation is also hesitating. Ambivalence, ambiguity,<br />

uncertainty, and plasticity bother humans groping their way toward phenomena that


DO SCIENTIFIC OBJECTS HAVE A HISTORY/ 8'<br />

are in themselves secure.li But ambivalence (etc.) also accompanies creacures to which<br />

the laboratory offers the possibility ofexistence, a historic opportunity. Fermenrarion<br />

has experienced other lives before now (1817) and eisewhere, but its new concrescence<br />

is a unique, dated, localized life made up in part sf p256sru-himself transformed by<br />

his second great discovery-and in part of the laboratory. By speaking of events de-<br />

fined in terms of their relations, I am sketching here the history of Pasteur and his<br />

yeast, ofthe yeast and l/s Pasteur.<br />

FRolr rsn EveNr ro rHE SussraNcs<br />

By describing in this way the shared history ofa researcher, a discipline, a laboratory,<br />

a lixture, a yeast, and a theory, one does not for all that lose the substance and its<br />

attribuces, but the meaning of the word substance changes profoundly and becomes the<br />

gradual attribution ofstable properties attached by an instirution to a name lastingly<br />

linked to a practice, the whole circulating in a relatively standardized network. This<br />

transition from the event to the newly defrned substance poses a formidable problem<br />

of description and interpretation from which Pasteur extricates himself through two<br />

apparent contradictions.<br />

At the beginning of his report, the author does not yet know which properties to<br />

attribute to which essences. By the end, the yeast possesses the same solidity as rhar of<br />

brewer's yeastr recently discovered. The substance endowed with attributes offers a<br />

parricular case of the event deÊned by its relations, a manner of summarizing, of rou-<br />

tinizing, of stabilizing, of institutionalizing events. It is as though one began with<br />

attributes before coming to an essence. Let us take this transition, rarely studied, be-<br />

cween two completely different ontological states summed up in two paragraphs of<br />

Pasteur's report:<br />

Ler us consider nlu ahat are the characteristics of this stbstance, rhe prldactizn 0f<br />

u,bich goes band in band u,ith tbose phenomena that, taken T0getber, we call lacticfernren-<br />

tation. Yiewed as a mass lr looks exactl like ordinary pressed ttr drained yeast. lt is<br />

sligbtly uiscous, and gray in color Under the microscope, it appears to be formeà af<br />

litt/e globul,es oruery sbort segmentedfi/aments, isolated or in clusters, u,hichform irregu-<br />

lar faku<br />

resembling those of certain antorpboas precipitates. lt can be co\Iected and<br />

transported for great distances withoat losing lrs actiuity, u,hich is weakened only<br />

tahen the material ls dried or u,hen lr ls boiled in u,ater. Very lictle of tbis yast is<br />

nece:sdry /a transform a nnsiderable weight of sagar. . . .<br />

t-It<br />

is the mistake ofsocial constructivists to accord inwpretiufexibilil_y only ro researchers acrively<br />

engaged with the data. To introduce nonhumans would always amount, according to him, to silencing<br />

controversies. Inversely, Hacking has no difliculty giving a constructivist reading of social facts since it is<br />

understood, once and for all, that they can correspond to norhing but arbitrary, self-realizing prophecies.<br />

Ian Hacking, "Vorld-Making by Kind-Making: Child Abuse for Example," in Hau. ClassiJiation tYorks:<br />

Nelson Goodntan Amang the Sodal Sùencr, ed. Nelson Goodman, Mary <strong>Do</strong>uglæ, and David L. Hull (Edin-<br />

burgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1992), 180-231.


86 COMMON KNOWLEDGE<br />

,'Hae ue fnd<br />

all the general characteristics of breuer's \east, and these substances<br />

probablT hate organic sftuctales that, in a nataral classiÊcation, place then in neigh-<br />

boring species or in tut connected hmilies " (Emphasis added')<br />

In rhe frrst patagraph, rhe essence is defrned only by various trials to which one<br />

submits the anonymous "special substance," recording resPonses that have fecently<br />

become stable thanks ro rhe care and skill ofthe scienrist and to the laboratory's genius<br />

loci. Each trial brings a new surprise: "x" can be transported without weakening! so<br />

litrle "x" is needed to transform so much sugar! Still, attributes float without being<br />

able to attach themselves ro a substratum. one senses in the text Pasteur's hesitarions,<br />

scruples, shilly-shallying before a viscous, Sray matter that resists dryness and boiling'<br />

The trial defines it in all its freshness, as though, to use the vocabulary of semiotics,<br />

one could induce competences only on the bâsis of troublingperformances.<br />

But in the nexr paragfaph, the coalescence has taken place. The "special substance"<br />

no longer merely fesembles brewer's yeast, it is no longer merely composed of globules,<br />

ofirregular flakes. The yeasr, now named, becomes a substance and occupies a clearly<br />

locatable position in a classification by family and by species. The attributes that<br />

floated randomly become rhe marks of an enduring essence-not simply of a stabilized<br />

routine like the iactic acid with which we began'<br />

How can we explain the transition from a long series of hesitant trials to a being<br />

summed up in a name? The answer of those historians o[science who are inspired by<br />

the firsc principle of symmetry leaves no doubt..\Tithout PresuPPosrn8 an organtsm'<br />

Pasteur never could have reduced up the long list of trials into a single yeasc' Ac-<br />

cording to hisrorians of science since Duhem, one has in fact always needed a theory a<br />

prejudice, a PresuPposition' a concepcual framework, a paradigm' in order to organize<br />

data that one can never encounter face to face: the inevitable return to Kant and his<br />

sociologisr followers. curiously, Pasteur asks himself the same question and seems to<br />

espouse the constructivist thesis before contradicting himselfa second time:<br />

All throagh this menoir, I haue teæoted on the basis of the hypothuis that the rygu yedrt<br />

is organized, that it is a liuing organism, and That its chemical action on sagar corresponds<br />

to itt deuelopment and organization. If someone weft t0 tell ne that in these conclasions I<br />

am going beyond that which the facts prot,e, I uould answa that this is quite ffae' in the<br />

sense that the scand I am taking is in a framework of ideas that in rigorots terms<br />

cannot be in{utab\ demonstrated. Hae is the way I see it; u'bern'er a chemist makes<br />

a stady of these nysterioas pbenomena and has tl:e goodfortune to bring aboat an intp|rtant<br />

deuelopment, he uill instinctively be inclined t0 asriSn its primary cal'/re t0 a t\pe of<br />

reaction consistent sttth the genaal resalts of his oun reseatclt. It is the logical course of<br />

tbe human ntind in all controtasial questions' (Emphasis added )<br />

In rhe purest (French) rarionalisr tradition, Pasteur insrsts on the necessity of a<br />

theory in order to make facts speak and, in the same breath, brings rnto play practical


DO SCIENTIFIC OBTECTS HAVE A HISTORYT 87<br />

training in chemistry, instinctive inclinations, the "logical course" of the human mind,<br />

and personal perspective. He knows that one must follow reason to find the facts. But,<br />

in spite of the superÊcial resemblance to social constructivists, there is nothing in<br />

Pasteur's rhetoric to enchant them because, without fear of contradicting himself,<br />

Pasteur goes on to the most traditional realism, and tranquilly afÊrms:<br />

And it is ny opinion, at this point in tlse deuelopnent of my knowledge of the sabject, tbat<br />

whoever jadges impartially the resalx of this u,ork and that which I shall shortly pab-<br />

lish wrI\ recognize with me that fermentatizn appears to lte correlatiue to life and to<br />

the organization of globulu, and noT to their death or putrefaction. Any contention that<br />

fetmentation is a phenomenon due to contact in which the transformation of vgar takes<br />

place in the presence of tbe ferment without giuing up arything to it or taking dryTbing<br />

from it, is contradicted by experiment as will be soon seen. (Emphasis added.)<br />

Give me impartial colleagues, he says, and they will recognize what the experiment<br />

incontestably affirms-the same experiment that had required after-the-fact presup-<br />

positions without which the presence of microorganisms couid not be demonstrared.<br />

Pasteur ignores this flagrant contradiction and moves from a realist to a construcrionisc<br />

epistemology in much the way that the yeast smoothly moves from event to substance.<br />

Before reading Whitehead, I could not extricate myself from this dilemma. It<br />

seemed that we always had to choose between two evils: S7hitehead opens a new possi-<br />

biliry and allows us to understand why the contradiction is only apparent. Lactic-acid<br />

yeast changes its history upon contact wich Pasteur and his laboratory. It is quite real,<br />

but its historical reality puts it on an equal footing with the researcher and the labora-<br />

tory in which it is involved. Lactic acid has also changed. The yeast has taken the little<br />

push that Pasteur has given it as a historic opportunity to manifest itself by altering<br />

its entire trajectory. The yeast proposes, Pasteur disposes. Pasteur proposes, the yeast<br />

disposes. Pasteur has not imposed his views on an infinitely plastic form, nor tenta-<br />

tively discovered the resistance of an infrnitely robust form; he has given a phenome-<br />

non its chance. This is why, writing his report, he sees no contradiction between his<br />

realist and constructivist rhetoric, though everything discinguishes them in the eyes<br />

of an epistemologist or a social historian. An ontology, even more counterintuitive<br />

than that of the sociai historv of science. allows us to foilow the common sense of<br />

a scientist:<br />

The experinenter, a man of conquest ûuer natilre, finds bimself cease/ess/y at grips uitb<br />

facts that are nlt let manifested and exist, for the most part, only potentially in<br />

natural Iaw. The unknown in the bossible and not in wbat has been-this is his donain,<br />

(Emphasis<br />

added.)'8<br />

r3louis<br />

Pasteur, Oeares complètes,7 vols. (Paris: Mæson, 1939), 7:)34.-Trans. L. Dauit


88 COMMON KNOlYLEDGE<br />

Tbsrso sy lùfHrrrFreRo<br />

Vhy does positing the historicity of all things, even though this solution may in che<br />

end be reconciled with common sense, appear at lirsc sight so unlikely, so senseless2<br />

Because ofour ideas about nature, about transcendence, and about causality, ideas that<br />

l7hitehead allows, profoundly, to dismiss.<br />

Suppose we were to calculate the ingred.ients rhat enter into rhe composition of<br />

Iactic yeast of I8)7 in order to understand the coproducrion of this scientific fact.<br />

Once the accounts ofdiscovery in the old mode have been abandoned, along with the<br />

more recent accounts ofsocial construction, we musr draw up a heterogeneous list thar<br />

includes, among many other factors, Pasteur, the Faculty of Science at Lille, Liebig,<br />

cheesemongers, laboratory appararus, brewer's yeasr, sugar, and lactic yeasr. There is<br />

no essentialism in this list since each entity is defined only by its relations. If the<br />

relations change, the definition changes similarly; rhe Faculty of Science with and<br />

without Pasceur is not exactly the same Faculty; sugar with and without lactic yeast is<br />

not quite the same sugar; lactic yeast after and before 18)7 is not ar all the same yeasc.<br />

But history cannot be defined by a simple rearrangement of factors. <strong>History</strong> is not<br />

created from already made ingredienrs. To avoid rhe jangling of combinations, rhe<br />

atomism of factors, we must thus recognize in every compound, in every concrescence,<br />

something more, some rad.ical and unique capacity for innovation-and, to do so, we<br />

must accept the fact that events, to deserve their name, are in part without cause.<br />

As absurd as that appears, realism demands that one abandon rhe idea of causality as<br />

compulsory movement or as a displacement of forms. The discovery of lactic yeast.in<br />

1857 is not due to a dispersal of infinitesimai conditions that defr calculation but of<br />

which each, nevertheless, acts as a cause. For there to be history, the yeast-of-1817-at-<br />

Lille-with-Pasteur must in part be caasa sui,te<br />

Nowhere in the universe does one find a cause, a compulsory movement, that per-<br />

mics one to surn up any event in order to explain irs emergence rerrospectively. If it<br />

were otherwise, one would not be faced with an event, with a difference, but only wirh<br />

the simple activation of a potential, the mere actualization of a cause.'u Time would /a<br />

nothing and history would be in vain. The discovery-invention-construction of lactic<br />

yeast requires that it be given the status ofa mediation, that is, ofan occurrence that<br />

is neither altogether a cause nor aitogether a consequence, nor completely a means nor<br />

completely an end.<br />

Pasteur can be understood as an event occurring to lactic yeasr because he is unfore-<br />

'e"All actual entities share with God this characteristic of self-causation. For this reason every actual<br />

entity also shares with God the characteristic of transcending all other actual entities, including God."<br />

\Thitehead, 223.<br />

'oThis is also the argumenr of the most Whiteheadian French philosopher, Deleuze. See especially Gilles<br />

Deleuze, Le Pli: Leibniz et lc baroqrc (Paris: Minuit, 1988), and the remarkable small book by François Zourabicâvili,<br />

Deleuze. ane philoupbie dz I'rh,énment (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1994).


DO SCIENTIFTC OBJECTS HAVE A HISTORY? 89<br />

seen, external to the history that until then defrned the "society" of the microorganism,<br />

its trajectory its heritage. To 6nd itselfin a laboratory there co be scattered, cultivated,<br />

redescribed, purifred, diverts the yeast in an unpredictable way. At the same time, the<br />

lasring presence of a yeast associated with a fermentation, the chemical acûvity of a<br />

living creature, constitutes, for Pasteur, a decisive branching out ofhis career and iden-<br />

tity. As for the chemists, by accepting Pasteur and his yeast, they become, through a<br />

decisive rranslacion, biochemists. No ingredient, as we can see, enters into these rela-<br />

tions wirhout changing its nature.<br />

As long as one made nature the kingdom of causes, to speak of a historicity of<br />

tbings seemed improbable: inventiveness, flexibility, hesitation, could only come from<br />

humans and their painful history. They alone could transcend the brutal realm of ob-<br />

jects, affirm their freedom against the viscous constraints ofthe "practico-inert," to use<br />

Sarrre's expression for the antipodes of freedom. By linking humans and nonhumans,<br />

the principle of generalized symmetry causes a small scandal, since it amounts to ex-<br />

tending rhe notion of personhood to creatures of nature-panpsychism, hylozorsm-<br />

or, on rhe other hand, co plunging human invention into the more or less predictable<br />

game of cause5-ms6h2nism, social engineering.2r<br />

\ù(hat a difference it would make if all entities left behind. transcended, exceeded<br />

ro some degree their causes, their histories, their ancestries! The objects of nature no<br />

longer offer as their only ontological model the stubborn, obstinate, headstrong, silent<br />

demand ofsubstance. Nothing thus prevents us from granting them a role in the fabri-<br />

carion of the human world, and doing so does not require our returning to the old-<br />

style realism that social historians rightly fought, nor does it open us to the accusation<br />

ofgranting to nonhumans that intentional personality heretofore reserved for humans.<br />

Nature shares with society the same historicity, but the uniÊed whole does nor become<br />

either immanent or transcendent, impersonal or personal, animated or inanimate. The<br />

transcendence necessary co innovarion is distributed through all the little uncouplings<br />

through which effects leave behind their causes. The history ofscience becomes once<br />

and for all an existentialism extended to things. Nature, by becoming historical,22 be-<br />

comes even more lnteresting, more realistic.<br />

As for nature's contrary, culture, ic is transformed even more thoroughly, and may<br />

be reconciled more completely with common sense. In culture, one is therefore not<br />

2rThe<br />

transition from cause-and-effect analysis to a conception of order through disorder has curiously<br />

not changed chis alrernative, despite Ilya Prigogine and I. Stengers, Eiltre le îemps et /'étrnité (Paris: Fayarà,<br />

1988). The notion ofemergence, rhough very \ùThrteheadian, does not necessarily imply the symmerrical<br />

historicization of nature and societr.<br />

"This hisroricity musr nor be confused with a transformation in rime of particles or living crearures<br />

such as are discussed in cosmological or evolutionist accounts a, for instance, Stephen Jay Gould, tVondafal<br />

Life: The Burgess Shale and the Nature of Histar;'(New York: !7. W. Norton, 1989). Inverting the anthropic<br />

principle cames scientists to enter the history of things. One not only recounts how the dinosaurs disappeared<br />

but also how paleontologists participate in the very history of the dinosaurs-two complementary<br />

but distinct historiciries.


forever a prisoner oflanguage, locked into conceptual frameworks, forever deprived of<br />

all access to things themselves, on which, as for Kant, we could only impose arbitrary<br />

categories. Our minds, our societies, our paradigms are no longer so many closed<br />

circles. Despite his hesitations, Pasteur does not dictate to the facts how they should<br />

speak. He ningles with them. He does not discover them any more than he fashions<br />

them.<br />

\Whitehead pleasantly makes fun of philosophers who believe our minds ate con-<br />

nected to the world by the fragile footbridge of perception alone, as though a grc^r<br />

city, until then open to the surrounding countryside, had decided to enclose itself<br />

gradually behind ramparcs, permirting no passage except by way of a narrow Postern<br />

gate and a shaky drawbridge. All philosophy of knowledge arises, he argues, from this<br />

artifuially maintained fragrlity, as though rhe mind constantly risked losing its pre-<br />

cious provisions. But if you demolish the ramparts, authorize other passages, open<br />

wide the city to the countryside, do away with city taxes. contacts between the mind<br />

and the world will not be lacking. There is no risk o[ an embargo on importations,<br />

since, no longer ascetics, we would no longer be obliged to deprive ourselves of sum-<br />

moning the things ofnature, which would then be broadly accessible because transcen-<br />

dent like us, historical like us, heterogeneous like us.<br />

By sharing transcendence with objects and gaining access to them through the<br />

thousand conduirs oflanguage, ofpractice, ofsocial life, we are no longer bound to file<br />

items exclusively under the heading of nature or society or discourse. It is enough to<br />

place rhem in "networks"-but while that word used to be employed in a vague sense,<br />

it can have, thanks to \ùThitehead,<br />

the ontology of its ambitions. Every item or circum-<br />

stance exactly lills, withouc suppiement or residue, its unique spatioternporal enve-<br />

lope. There exists nothing, not lactic yeast, not universal gravitation, that "would over-<br />

flow" the historical conditions of its emergence-which does not mean, however, that<br />

everything is rhe result of human work alone, as social constructivists feel always<br />

obliged to conclude. Again, we do not have to choose between these two versions. In<br />

order for an item or circumstance to extend and thus give the impression of "overflow-<br />

ing," it requires other historical conditions, other vehicles, other mediations, other<br />

underpinnings-each partially causes of themselves.<br />

'We<br />

would not find this historicrzation diffrcuh except that we make unconsidered<br />

use of the two pairs of adverbs a/u'a1's/na,er anà n,ery,71'/ttr't1rru'bere. Since the emergence<br />

in 1817 of lactic acid, we have concluded that it has alu,als been there and that it<br />

acts equally a'ulwhere. From the time of Pasteur's destruction of Liebig's theory about<br />

fermentation rhrough degradation of substances, we have concluded that it has neuer<br />

been present, anyu,/tere-a double exaggeration that makes the history of things co-<br />

alesce and then obliges one to invent, by contrast, those accounts of discovery that I<br />

criticized at the opening ofthis essay. Because yeast has always existed, a fact unknown<br />

before 1817, Pasteur musr necessarily have discovered ir by lifting a veil that concealed<br />

it. But Pasteur, his colleagues, the cheesemongers, the dairies, the historians, must


DO SCIENTIFIC OBJECTS HAVE A HISTORY? 9I<br />

work hard in order to extend into the past the retrospective presence of lactic-acid<br />

yeast. Scientists and historians work like software companies that, for a modest sum,<br />

will replace version 2.1 of your program with the new version 2.2,retrofrtttng all the<br />

new advances without (so you hope) endangering your earlier programs. In the case of<br />

the iactic-acid yeast, enormous work is necessary also in space as weil as time to extend<br />

to all dairies and cheese manufacturers the presence, soon "universal," of lactic yeasr.<br />

Still more work must be done to eliminate Liebig's version from history and gradualiy<br />

eliminare it from scientific 112nu215-until the "discovery" of enzymes, later in the<br />

century, which newly reshapes fermentation, Pasteur, Liebig, and the retrospective his-<br />

tory ofbiochemistry. Lactic yeast, in the course ofits history, never exaggerates either<br />

its existence or nonexistence, its locality or universality. Like other entities, it perse-<br />

veres in its being, however tiny, in certain places, for a certain time, on condition of<br />

existing in common with many others that also decline to acquiesce either to substance<br />

or nothingness, but "decide," at the turning points, on their history. Like frbers, lin-<br />

eages, trajectories, heritages, societies, rhizomes.<br />

I hope that I have shown, as I promised, thac \Whitehead's metaphysics allows us to<br />

help the philosophy of the history of science-blocked for some time on the question<br />

of the role that ought to be given to nonhuman5-1e salçs a small step forward. It is<br />

perfectly possible to reconcile skepticism and realism, provided historicity be thor-<br />

oughly granted to nonhumans as well. A little historicity spawns reiativism, a grcat<br />

deal ensenders realism.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!