Academia.eduAcademia.edu
8 Jacques Derrida on the Ethics of Hospitality Gerasim os Kakoliris Introduction "You're probably surprised to find us so inhospitable," said the man, "but hospitality isn't a custom here, and we don't need any visito rs."1 If th is quotat ion from Kafka's Castle seems strange to us, it is because we ca nnot believe that there is a cultu re, a society or "a form of social connection without a principle of hospitality. ,,2 But what is left of this pri nciple of hospitality today, or ethics in general, when fences are erected at the borders, or even "hospitality" itself is considered a crime? In "Derelictions of the Right to Justice (But what are the 'sans-papier' Lacking?)," concern ing the clumsy and violent imposition of the Debret la ws on immigrants and those wi thout ri gh ts of residence, the so-ca lled "sans-papier," wh ich provoked mass demonstrations of protest in Paris,3 Derrida wri tes, I remember a bad day last year: It just about took my breath away, it sickened me when I heard the exp ression for the first time, barely understanding it, the expression crime ofllOspitality [delitd'hospitalitej. In fact, I am not sure th at I heard it, because I wonder how anyone could ever have pronounced it [ ... J no, I d id not hea r it, and I can barely repeat it; I read it voicelessly in an official text. It concerned a law permitting the prosecution, and even the imprison men t, of those who take in and help foreigners whose status is held to be illegal. This "crime of hospita lity" (I still wonder who dared to put these words together) is punishable by imprisonment. What becomes of a country, one must wonder, what becomes of a culture, what becomes 144 Jacques Derrida on tlle Etllics of Hospitality 145 of a language when it admits of a "crime of hospitality," when hospitality can become, in the eyes of the law and its representatives, a criminaloffense?4 This perplexity provoked Derrida's thoughts on the Ethics of Hospitality. For Derrida, the logic of the concept of hospitality is governed by an absolute antinomy or aporia. On the one hand, there is the law of unlimited hospitality that ordains the unconditional reception of the stranger. On the other hand, there are the conditional laws of hospitality, which rela te to the unconditional la w through the imposition of terms and conditions (pol itical, juridical, moral) upon it. For Derrida, the responsible action and decision consists of the need to continuously negotiate between these two heterogeneous requirements. In this chapter, I identify a problem with Derrida's position, which is that it resorts to the use of terms such as "pure," "real," "genuine" or "absolute," in order to describe unconditional hospitality and to differentiate it from conditional hospitality. Yet, such terms have been placed into question by deconstruction itself. Moreover, the disjunctive distinction that Derrida installs, at an initial level, between "unconditional" and "conditional" hospitality contradicts the work which he had undertaken during the 1960s and the 1970s of deconstructing basic conceptual hierarchical binary oppositions that govern Western metaphysical thought. Against the rather problematic guiding concept of "unconditional" hospitality, I then propose a con tinuous, incessant effort of limiting violence towards the arriving stranger. My argument draws from the particularly insightful remarks of Derrida regarding the violence that inescapably resides in every act of hospitality as a result of the host's exercise of sovereignty over his/her home. Derrida on unconditional and conditional hospitality During the 1990s, and until his death in October 2004, the French philosopher Jacques Derrida (1930-2004) wrote extensively on the ethics of hospitality.5 Derrida often identifies a concept from the Western heritage and employs it to address critically a specific and concrete context. In this case, it is the rising hostility of European governments towa rds immigrants. In an analysis that is at once historical, conceptual, and thematic, Derrida attempts to bring out the logic that governs the concept of hospitality. The logic that Derrida identifies as conditioning the concept of hospitality within Western tradition takes the form of a tenSion, a contradiction, an antinomy or a double imperative. On the one 146 Gemsimos Kakoliris hand, there is the law of unlimited hospitality that ordains the unconditional reception of the other, whoeve r he or she is: that is, the provision of hospitality to a stranger without conditions, restrictions and returns. The law of absolute, pure, unconditional, hyperbolic hospitality, asks us to say "yes" to the newcomer [arrivantJ, before any determination, before any prevention, before any identification - irrespective of being a stranger, an immigrant, a guest or an unexpected visitor. On the other hand, there are the conditional laws (in the plural) of hospitality, which, while they establish a right to and a duty in hospitality, they simultaneously place terms and conditions on hospitality (political, juridical, moral), ordaining that this right should be given always under ce rtain conditions: as, for example, that they should exist certain restrictions in the right of entry and stay of the foreigner. Moreover, the reciprocity of the commitment that conditions this notion of hospitality entails that the foreigner does not only have a right: he or she also has, reciprocally, obligations, as it is often recalled, when someone wishes to reproach him or her for bad behavior. The right to hospitality subsumes the reception, the welcome that is given to th e foreigner under a strict and restrictive jurisdiction. From t he point of view of a right to hospitality, the guest, even when he or she is well received, is mainly a foreigner; he or she should remain a foreigner. Certainly, hospitality is a debt to the guest, but it remains condition ed and conditional. If, for example, he or she does not possess a right to hospitality or a right to asylum, each new arrival is not accepted as a guest. Without this right, he or she can enter one's "home," the "house" of the host, only as a "pa rasitize" - as illegal, clandestine, subject to arrest or deportation. In the context of unconditional hospitality, Derrida makes special reference to lmmanuel Kant, who, in the third article entitled "The Law of World Citizenship Shall Be limited to Cond itions of Universal Hospitality" of his essay Towards Perpetual Peace, defines "universal hospitality" as the right of a stranger not to be treated as an enem y when he arrives in the land of another. One may refuse to receive him when this can be done without causing his destruction; but, so long as he peacefully occupies his place. one may not treat him with hostility.(i In addition, Kant limits the right to hospitality to a "ri gh t of visit," in virtue of an initial common possession of the surface of earth, and not to a "right of residence (a right of residence would presuppose a special convention between nation-states, demanding that the foreigner is a jacqlles Derrida 011 the Ethics of Hospitality 147 citizen of another nation·state) . To Kant's IIconditional" hospitality, Derrida will oppose lIunconditional" or "pure" hospitality, which is without conditions and wh ich does not seek to ident ify the newco mer, even if he is not a citizen. For Derrida, absolu te or unconditional hospitality presupposes a rupture with hospitality under the current sense, wit h conditional hospitality, with the right to or pact of hospitality. As he explains in Of Hospitality: ... absolute hospitality requires that I open up my home and that I give not only to the foreigner (p rovided with a family name, with the social status of being a fo reigner, etc.), but to the absolute, unknown, anonymous other, and th at I give place to them, that I let them come, that I let them arri ve, and take place in the place I offer them, without asking of them either reciprocity (en tering in to a pact) or even thei r names. 7 Derrida reminds us that, even though hospitality begins with the questi on that someone addresses to the person that comes (so mething that appea rs very human and occasio nally expresses love: "tell me you r name, what sho uld I call you, I who am call ing o n you, I who wa nt to call you by you r name?"),8 nevertheless, the fo reigner, according to the laws of conditi onal hospitality, is somebody to whom, in order to receive him o r her, someone begins by placing the question about his or her name: he or she orda ins him or her to declare hi s or her identity and to give guar· antees about it. To ask, however - to learn who th e other is, to ask for the other to be iden tified before I accept or reject my obligation to welcome him or her - means to render my moral obligation conditional on me and my know led ge of the other. Hospitality, nevert heless, in order to be "real," "true" hospitality, should not discriminate. It should be open to indiscriminate otherness even if it risks always opening the door to its own undoing. In this sense, "pure" hospitality is a risk, because we cannot determine who will be our guest or how he or she will behave as a guest. Consequently, hospitality, for Derrida, obeys the fo llowing paradox with regard to whether we should or should not ask questions, to call someone by his or her name or not: Hospitality presupposes the call o r the mnemonic recall of th e proper name in its pure possibility ("it's to you, yo urself, that I say 'come,' 'enter"'), and at the same time the obliteration of the proper name itself (If/come,' 'enter,' 'whoever you are and whatever your name, you r language, your sex, you r species may be, be you human, an imal, or divine ... "').9 148 Gerasim05 Kakoliris Even though these two regimes of hospitality - the unconditional law of hospitality, in its universal singularity, and th e conditional (plural) laws of hospitality - are heterogeneous, irreducible, they do, however, resemble each other. This is because, on the one hand the conditional la ws of hospitality would cease to be laws of hospitality if they were not guided by the law of unconditional hospitality: if they were not inspired by it, if they did not aspire to it, if, indeed, they did not demand it. Political and moral action needs to be related to a moment of unconditional or infinite responsibility in o rder not to be reduced to the demands of the moment: that is, it should be based on a moment of universality that exceeds the pragmatic demands of a certa in context. Therefore, the laws of hospitality need the law of absolute hospitality in order to place them and to keep them in an incessant progressive movement/ to improve them. On the other hand, without the conditional laws of a right and a duty to hospitality, the law of unconditional hospitality would be in danger of remaining abstract, ineffective, wishful thinking, utopian. In order to be what it is - namely, an ought to be - the law should become existent, effective, concrete, determined. Consequently, it needs the laws, which, nevertheless - through the determination of limits, powers, rights and duties - threaten, corrupt or "pervert" it. For Derrida, the "pervertibility" of the law of hospitality arises from the comp licity between trad itional hospitality, hospitality in the current sense, and power. There is no hospitality, in the classical sense of the term, without the sovereignty of the person who offers hospitality in his or her house. Therefore, there is an essential "self-restraint" incorporated in the idea of hospitality that maintains the distance between what belongs to the host and the foreigner, between the power of the host to remain master of his or her house and the invitation of the other into it. As John Caputo observes in Deconstruction in a Nutshell: When the host says to the guest, "Make yourself at home," this is a self-limiting invitation. "Make yourself at home" means: please feel at home, act as if you were at home, but, remember, that is not true, this is not you r home but mine, and you are expected to respect my property. 10 Since there is no hospitality without time restrictions (it is not possible to come to your place as a visitor and stay there forever), or Without numerical restrictions (if you invite me to your place, I cannot bring all my relatives and friends), the host exercises his or her sovereignty by lacques Derrida on the Ethics of Hospitality 149 selecting, filtering, choosing his or her guests or visitors - by deciding who to offer the right of hospitality to, and also by fixing the period over which they can stay. Thus, there is always a certain hostility in every act of hospitality: that is, hospitality always brings within itself its opposite, a certain "hostipit.lity."This is also reflected in its etymology: The word "hospitality" stems from th e Latin hospes, which is formed from the word hostis, initially meaning a "stranger/' and afterwards received the meaning of enemy or "hostile" stranger (hostilis), plus the word pets (potis, pates, potentia)to have power. J I Therefore, excluSion, unfairness, a certain violence, or even "perjury" towards the absolute law of hospitality, begins immediately, from the threshold of the right to hospitality. Nevertheless, Derrida recognizes that, without the possession of a home (which, indeed, limits hospitality) there is in reality no door to hospitality - no right and no subsequent debt. The exercise of possession over one's /t home" is not ultimately negative since it yields the possibility of hospitality - though not in an absolute, unconditional form. What is required, according to Derrida, is a continuous 'Inegotiation" or IIcompromise," which one has always to invent, between the wish to have and retain a house or a country, and the renunciation of one's mastery over it. Derrida writes in Echographies of Television (1996): When we say negotiation, we say compromise, transaction [ ... J Transactio n is necessary in the name of the intractable, in the name of the unconditional, in the name of something that admits of no transaction, and that's the difficulty. The difficulty as "political" difficulty.1 2 For Derrida, this asymmetry between conditional and unconditional hospitality maintains an endless demand, since each event ofweJcoming the other can only fall short of the reqUirements of the unconditional law of unlimited hospitality. Whatever decision we make in relation to the arrival of a stranger, the infinite obligation to welcome the other, whoever he o r she is, will always exist, and will exceed the apparently justified restrictions and conditions that we place on the other in his or her arrival and stay. Responsible action and decision consists in the necessity of an incessant negotiation between the law of unconditional hospitality - wh ich disregards right, duty or even politics - and ordains a welcome to the newcomer beyond any terms and conditions. The laws of hospitality - through the determination of limits, powers, rights and duties - defy and violate the law of un conditional hospitality. 150 Gerasimos Kakoliris The decision of hospitality, accord ing to Oerrida, asks me each time to invent my own rule. If I want to appear hospitable to a guest or an unexpected visitor, my behavior - and this is a condition of any moral responsibility - should not be dictated, programed or arranged by nothing, which would be used as a rule that is applied mechanically. Otherwise, I can appear hospitable even when I have not chosen to be. According to Derrida's anti-normative ethics, on ly when somebody starts from nothing - that is, from no previous ru le o r norm - does the "inventive" or "poetic" event of hospitality ha ve some possibility of occuring. In order for a real event of hospitality to take place, it is necessary to make the "impossible" possi ble. [n "As If it were Possible, Within Such Limits," Oerrida writes, When the impossible makes itself possible, the eve nt takes place (possibility of the impossible). That, indisputably, is the paradoxical form of the event: if an event is only possible, in th e classic sense of this word, if it fits in with conditions of possibility, if it only makes explicit, unveils, revea ls, or accomplishes that whi ch wa s already possible, then it is no lo nger an event. For an event to take place, for it to be pOSSible, it has to be, as event, as invention, the com ing of the impossible. 13 Critiquing Derrida's position In what follows, 1 examine some problems, which, I believe, arise from Derrida's treatment of the moral principle of hospitality. The first of my two ma in objections concerns th e distinction that Derrida makes between unconditio nal and conditional hospitality. Even though he says these two concepts are "inseparable, " he does not refrain - before declaring their inseparability - fro m separating them into two distinct possibilities. Either hospitality is unconditional or conditional; the o ne excl udes the other. Hence, the philosopher who has identified himself with the disclosure and deconstruction of the hierarchical binary ap positional logic of Western meta physics seems to have set up a binary opposition of his own. Derrida's first pOSSibili ty is identified wi th "purity" (" pure hospitality"), "truth" ("t rue hospitali ty") and the "absolute" ("absol ute hospita lity"), while the o pposite, un conditiona l hospitality, is identified with all th ose elements which threaten or contaminate the "purity" of the first. And if it should happe n that unconditional hospitality does intermix, even by necessity as Oerrida claims, with "conditions," in th e form of conditional hospitality, the n /ncqlles Derridn 011 the Ethics of Hospitality I SI this shou ld confirm (since, after all, we are speaking of "mixing"), the essential purity of its identity. It is quite paradoxical - and this is my second objection to Derrida's views on hospitality - to find him talking of "pure" hospitality, "real hospitality," "true" hospitality," when he is the philosopher par excellence who has put the concepts of "purity" and "tru th" under questio n. For Derrida, concepts such as, essence, truth, purity, are linked and grounded in the conception of an immediate presence (What he ca lls "metaphysics of presence"). Through the deconstructive readings that he undertoo k during the 1960s and 19705, he tried to show that absence and difference are not mere deviations from presence and identity but conditions of possibility for them (as well as cond itions of non-possibility of an absolute presence or identity). This is crystallized in his thought of differance which means simultaneously difference and deferral. In "Signature Event Context," Derrida attacks the idea of "purity," claiming that there is a "general iterability which const itutes a violatio n of the allegedly rigorous purity of every event of discourse or every speech act 14 ." Derr ida's claim is that there can be no identity without repetition. And yet, this very repetitio n puts in question the identity which it promotes - for th ere can be no repetition wit hout difference. From what has already been sa id, Derrida should have concluded the impossibility of the existence of a "pure" concept of hospitality: that the concept of hospitality, as with the concept of presence, is affected straight away by an essential disruption, impurity, corruption, contamination or prevention . In this sense, "impurity," in the form of conditio ns, is not a "supplement" which comes from outside to be added to an original, uncontaminated, pure hospitality. As Derrida himself has shown in his deconstruction of Rousseau, th e supplement is in the o rigin, renderin g the idea of an origin absurd. "Impurity" is always-a lready inscri bed in any act of hospitality due to its condition of possibility and imposSibility (hospitality as impossible in a pure, absolute, unconditional form). As a consequence, Derrida is right to conclude that every act of hospitality is conditioned by its opposite - a certain hostility; but he is wrong to cla im that we can presuppose something as "pure," "real" o r "true" hospitality. Another problem (or "advantage" for some) with Derrida's "hyperbolic" ethics o f hospitality is that it retains us in a permanent situation of "bad conscience," o r "guilt," The "absolute" or "hyperbolic" law of hospitality precludes someone from ever being hospitable enough. Therefore, o ne is always gu il ty and mu st always ask for forgiveness fo r never welcoming the other enough. Further, this applies to the fact 152 Gerasimos Knkoliris that th e hospita li ty offered can be rendered as a weapon - a confirmatio n of sovereignty, or even omnipotence, or an appeal for recognition, since If one always takes by giving." One must ask, therefore, a priori, forgive ness for the gift of hospitality, for the sovereignty o r the desire of sovereignty. IS Consequentl y, we see that such an ethics is not only run through by Kant ian ism - which views the ethical as purity of the will, and thus is unwi lling to examine something as eudemonistic as the act of hospitality - but it leaves us constantly with a feeli ng of gu ilt. As Derrida declares: ... if you think that the o nly moral duty you owe is the duty to the people - or the animals - with whom you have affinity, kinship, friendship, neighborh ood, brotherhood, then you can imagine the consequences of that. I, of course, have preferences. I am one of the common people who prefer th eir cat to th eir neighbor's cat and my fa mily to others. But I do not have a good conscience about that. I know that if I transform this into a general rule it would be the ruin of ethics. If I put as a principle that I wi ll feed first of all my cat, my family, my nation, that would be the end of any ethical poli. tics. So when I give a preference to my cat, which I do, that wil l not prevent me from ha ving some remorse for the cat dyi ng or starving next door, or, to change the example, for all the people on earth who are starving and dying today. So you cannot preven t me from having a bad conscience, and that is th e ma in motiva tion of my ethics and my polities. 16 Yet, we don't really know if the right response to an et hics of "good conscience" - to an ethics that puts clea r-cut limits to my responsibility so as to allow me to sleep easier and li ve with a clear conscience - is to substitute it with an ethicsof in finite responsibi lity, which leaves me with a "bad conscience." (l wou ld expect Derrida here to complicate things, rather than just oppose "good conscience" with "bad conscience.") It is true that there are few a priori limits to one's responsibility, but there are some (for example, I cannot feed all the starving children of the world). As David Wood remarks in "Responsibi lity Reinscr ibed (and How):" I am not a divine being [ ... J, but a mortal l... J, awa re of the fragility of every sense I might have of "what my situation is" or "what my responsibilities are.1! But equall y aware that to respond or act at all I cannot cease to be finite, situated, to have my own needs and limitations etc. [ ... ) our exposure to the other is not some huge, excessive Jncques Derri(/(I 011 tile Ethics of Hospitality 153 obligation, but rather a complex openness to requests, demands, pleas, which call not just for an acknowledgement of my obligations, but for scrutiny, for negotiation, for interpretation, and ultimately for recognizing both opportunities and limitations. I' Hence, just because there are no a priori limits to my responsibility does not necessarily mean that my responsibility is infinite, or that, as a resu lt, I should always feel "guilty" or "have a bad conscience." Here also I would dare to insist that one cannot have a pure sense of infinity (e.g. infinite responsibility) uncontaminated by the marginal, and vice versa. Moreover, it seems to me that, since such an ethics is "hyperbolic," it ends up saying that one never does anything ethical. In addition, what Derrida seems to overlook is that, in a sense, the more "absolute" or "hyperbolic" the ethics of hospitality is rendered, the more "unethical" it becomes. By ordaining the unconditional welcome of the stranger beyond the possibility of any discrimination, pure or absolu te hospitality can lead, not only to the destruction of one's home, but also to the suffering - or even death - of the host, since the guest could, for example, be a murderer or invader. This is a prospect that Derrida acknowledges but considers as unavoidable and surely not worth making him suspicious of his ethics of unconditional hospitality. He thus maintains, in "Hospitality, Justice and Responsibility": If, however, there is pure hospitality, or a pure gift, it should consist in this opening without horizon, without horizon of expectation, an opening to the newcomer whoever that may be. It may be terrible because the newcomer may be a good person, or may be the devil; but if you exclude the possibility that the newcomer is coming to destroy your house - if you want to control this and exclude in advance this possibility - there is no hospitality. In this case, you control the borders, you have customs officers, and you have a door, a gate, a key and so on. For unconditional hospitality to take place you have to accept the risk of the other coming and destroying the place, initiating a revolution, stealing everything, or killing everyone. That is the risk of pure hospitality and pure gift, because a pure gift might be terrible too. That is why exchan ge and controls and conditions try to make a distinction between good and evi l. Why did Kant insist on conditional hospitality? Because he knew that without these conditions hospitality could turn into wild war, terrible aggreSSion. Those are the risks involved in pure hospitality, if there is such a thing and I am not sure that there is. IS 154 Gerasimos Kakoliris Consequently, if "[fjor un conditional hospitality to take place you have to accept the risk of th e other coming and I... ] killing everyone," then one might ask if such a thing is really ethical. Here aga in, purity in ethics can be disastrous - or "monstrous" (to use Derrida's word). As Derrida contends in The Cift ofDeath, "I cannot respond to the ca ll, the demand, the obligation, or even the love of another without sacrificing the other other, the others others." 19 In this sense, speaking in Levinas' terms, the face-to-face ethical relationship will always be conta minated by the II third" - by the other's other. Moreover, as Martin Haglund remarks, if I did not discriminate between what I welcome and do not welcome, what I find acceptable and unacceptable, it would mean that I had renoun ced all claims to be responsible, make judgments, or pursue any critical refl ection at all."20 Of course, I agree with those who might claim that it is not always easy to say in advance who will be a good and or a bad visitor. There wou ld be no need for human decision iJ it were clear what is to be do ne - what is good and what is evil, who a saint and who a villain. In the First Book of Tile Republic, Socrates opposes Polemarchus' claim that "justice is to help your friends and harm your enemies" (334b), by saying: "But don't men often make mistakes, and thin k a man honest (christolls) when he is not, and vice versa?" (33 4c). Moreover, there is always the possibility of the "bad" visitor changing over time into a "good" one or vice versa. Hence, r would agree with Haglund that there are no criteria "that would aHow us to decide once and for all whether the other is good o r evil."21 Therefo re, the difficulty to differentiate is something that we ought to take into considerati on every time a decision needs to be made. AHdecision-making, all action, must be haunted by the shadow of a doubt: of a risk, of a feeling that we may be unjust to the other. In this sense, isn't xenophobia, among other things, a frivo lous, but also dangerous, attem pt to take all the agony, all the risk, out of a decision by always posing the foreigner as a threat? 11 ••• Conclusion Yet, if ethi cs is about responsibility, the ethics of unconditional hospitality would preclude us from taking any decision - and thus any responsib ility for ou r decisio ns. Uncondi tional hospitality req uires that r ca nnot react in a negative o r protectionist manner but must automaticall y welcome everything. Consequently, an eth ics of unconditional hospitality would short-circuit all decisions and be the sa me as a complete indifference to whatever happens. Decision is something that resides within the field of the conditional and not of the unco nditional. /acques De"ida Ul1 the Ethics of Hospitality 155 When Derrida talks in Echographies of Television, about the need of "negotiation," "compromise," "transaction" between unconditional and conditional hospitality - something that presupposes a decision - one shouldn't forget that all these belong to the domain of the conditional. Because, as Derrida himself emphasizes, the unconditional "admits of no transaction"22: that is, of no decisions. Hence, do we actually need a quasi-transcendental concept of unconditional hospitality? Do we really need a rather problematic ideal to guide us through the process of a decision? Does such a pronouncement presuppose the existence of an ideal of hospitality in the same way that, for Plato, the existence of certain criteria for judging something beautiful presupposed an eternal, absolute, objective Idea of beauty? Yet, isn't it enough just to say that the fewer conditions we put on our hospitality the more hospitable we are? Against the rather problematic gUiding concept of "unconditiona1" hospitality, I would prefer to concentrate on the particular instructive analyzes of Derrida concerning the various kinds of violence that necessarily condition every action of hospitality. This violence stems from the host's exercise of power and sovereignty over his or her house or country. My counter­position would be, therefore, a continuous, incessant effort of limiting violence towards the arriving foreigner. 23 Notes 1. F. Kafka (2009), The Castle, trans. Ant hea Bell, with an introd uctio n and notes by Ritchie Robertson (Oxford: Oxford University Press), p. 15. 2. j. Derrida (200S), "The Principle of Hospitality," in Paper Machine, traos. Rachel Bowlby (Stanfo rd, California: Stanford University Press), p. 66. 3. jean­Luis Debret was the French Minister of Foreign Affa irs at that time. 4. j. Derrida (2001), "Derelictions of the Right to just ice (But what are the 'sanspapier' lacking?), in Negotiations. Interventions and Interviews 1971-2001 , edited, trans., and with an introduction by Elizabeth Rottenberg, (Stanford, California: Stanford University Press), p. 133. S. Derrida devel o ps the question of hospitality mostly in the following texts: (1) j. Derrida (2000), Of Hospitality, trans. R. Bowl by (Stanford: Stanford University Press); (2) j. Derrida (1999), Adieu to Emmmwei Levinas, trans. P.­A. Brau lt &. M. Naas (Stanford: Sta nford University Press); (3) j . Derrida (1999), "Hospitality, justice and Responsibility: A Di alogue with jacques Derrida, " in Questioning Ethics: Contemporary Debates in Philosophy, ed. R. Kearney, M. Dooley (London: Routledge), pp. 65­83; (4) J Derrida (19 99), Autour de /acqll es Derrida. Manifes te pOllr !'hospitalite, ed. M. Seffahi (Pa ris: Paroles l'Aube); (5) J Derrida (2000), "Hospitality," Angeloki, 5 (3), pp. 3­18. (6) j. Derrida (2005), liThe Principle of Hospitality," in Paper Ma chine, trans. Rach el Bowlby, (Stanford, Ca lifornia: Stanford University Press), pp. 66­69; and (7) ). Oerrida (2002), "Hos pitality, " in Acts ofReJigioll, ed ited and wit h an introductio n by Gil An idjar (New York, London: Routledge), pp. 358­420. 156 Gerasimos Kakoliris 6. I. Kant (1988), "Perpetual Peace: A Philosophica l Sketch," in L. W. Beck (eds), Kallt. SelectiollS (Londo n: Co llier M acmillan Publishers), p. 439. 7. J. De rrida (2000), OfHospitaiity, p. 25. 8. Ib id., pp. 27. 9. Ibid ., pp. 137­ 139. 10. j. D . Ca puto (199 7), D econstruction ill a Nlltsl lCll: A Conversation with Jacql1es Derrida (N Y: Fordham Un iversity Press), p. 111. 11 . Derrida is following the ety mo logy of Emil Ben ven iste, i n (1969), Le vocablllaire des institutions illdo-europee1mes I (Paris: Minuit), chap. 7, "L'hospitalite." ・Lセ@ of Televis ioll: Filmed 12. j acq ues Derrida & Bernard Stiegler (2002) . e」 ャA ッァ イ。ーィゥ Il1terviews, t rans. Jennifer l3aj orek (Ox ford: Po lity Press), p. 8 1. 13. ). Derrida (200S), "As If it we re Possible, 'Within Such Limits,"' in Paper Machine, t ra ns. Rachel Bowlby (Stan fo rd, Ca li forn ia: Stan ford University Press), p. 90. 14. j. Derrida ( 1988), "Signature Event Context," in Limited lnc. (Evan ston, IL: Northwestern Uni versity Press), p. 18. I S. ). Derrida (2001), "Th e Unforgivable and the Imprescriptible," in j. Caputo, M . Dooley, & M. Scanlo n (eds), Questioning God (Bloomi ngton: Indiana University Press), p. 16. 16. j . Derrida (2001), liOn Forgive ness: A Roundrable Di scuss ion with jacques Derrida," in j. Caputo, M. Oooley, & M. Scan Io n (eds), Ql.lcsriollillg God (Bloomingh ton & lndianapolis: Indiana University Press), p. 48. 17. D. Wood (1997), " Responsib ility Reinscribed (and How)," in Jonathon Dronsfield & Nick M idgley (eds), Responsibilities ofDecol/s trllction, PLI Wnnv;ck Journ al a(Pllilasoplly 6, p. 110. 18. j. Derrida (1999), " Hospitality, ju stice and Responsibility: A Dialogue with j acques Derrida," pp. 70-7 1. 19. Ja cques Derrida ( 1993), Tile Gift of Death, trans. David W ill s (C hicago: Chicago Un iversity Press), p. 68. 20. Martin Haggl und (2008), Radical Atheism: Derridn and the Time Of Life (Stanford, Ca lifornia: Sta n ford Un iversity Press), p. 103. 2 1. Ibid., 125. 22. j. Oerr ida & B. St iegler (2002), Echagrnphies of Televisioll: Filmed interviews, p.81. 23. J would li ke to thank Dr Peter Langford for his invalua ble hel p.